-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 3
/
index.html
1385 lines (773 loc) · 181 KB
/
index.html
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
---
layout: main
based_on_commit: 1c953bc6a9ad8cc9908d2c855f5aec8fb2a21d12
title: What is Transhumanism?
description: Transhumanism is based on the premise that the human species in its current form is not the end of our development but rather a comparatively early phase.
localized_language_name: 'English'
translate_to_your_language: 'Translate to your language'
download_as_ebook: 'Download as e-book:'
for_ios_and_others: '(for iOS and others)'
for_kindle: '(for Kindle)'
---
<h1 class="headline"><em class="small">What is</em> <br>
Transhumanism?</h1>
<p class="print-only">{{ site.live_url }}</p>
<p id="#introduction"><strong>Transhumanism</strong> is a way of thinking about the future that is based on the premise that the human species in its current form does not represent the end of our development but rather a comparatively early phase.</p>
<p>Transhumanism is a loosely defined movement that has developed gradually over the past two decades.</p>
<blockquote>
<p>Transhumanism is a class of philosophies of life that seek the continuation and acceleration of the evolution of intelligent life beyond its currently human form and human limitations by means of science and technology, guided by life-promoting principles and values.</p>
– Max More (1990)
</blockquote>
<p><a href="https://www.humanityplus.org/">Humanity+</a> formally defines it based on Max More’s original definition as follows:</p>
<ol>
<li>The intellectual and cultural movement that affirms the possibility and desirability of fundamentally improving the human condition through applied reason, especially by developing and making widely available technologies to eliminate aging and to greatly enhance human intellectual, physical, and psychological capacities.</li>
<li>The study of the ramifications, promises, and potential dangers of technologies that will enable us to overcome fundamental human limitations, and the related study of the ethical matters involved in developing and using such technologies.</li>
</ol>
<p>Transhumanism can be viewed as an extension of humanism, from which it is partially derived. Humanists believe that humans matter, that individuals matter. We might not be perfect, but we can make things better by promoting rational thinking, freedom, tolerance, democracy, and concern for our fellow human beings. Transhumanists agree with this but also emphasize what we have the potential to become. Just as we use rational means to improve the human condition and the external world, we can also use such means to improve ourselves, the human organism. In doing so, we are not limited to traditional humanistic methods, such as education and cultural development. We can also use technological means that will eventually enable us to move beyond what some would think of as “human”.</p>
<h3 class="h2" id="about"><a href="#about">About the Transhumanist FAQ</a></h3>
<p>The Transhumanist FAQ was developed in 1998 and authored into a formal FAQ in 1999 through the inspirational work of transhumanists, including Alexander Chislenko, Max More, Anders Sandberg, Natasha Vita-More, James Hughes, and Nick Bostrom. Several people contributed to the definition of transhumanism, which was originated by Max More. Greg Burch, David Pearce, Kathryn Aegis, and Anders Sandberg kindly offered extensive editorial comments. The presentation in the cryonics section was, and still is, directly inspired by an article by Ralph Merkle. Ideas, criticisms, questions, phrases, and sentences to the original version were contributed by (in alphabetical order): Kathryn Aegis, Alex (intech@intsar.com), Brent Allsop, Brian Atkins, Scott Badger, Doug Bailey, Harmony Baldwin, Damien Broderick, Greg Burch, David Cary, John K Clark, Dan Clemensen, Damon Davis, Jeff Dee, Jean-Michel Delhotel, Dylan Evans, EvMick@aol.com, Daniel Fabulich, Frank Forman, Robin Hanson, Andrew Hennessey, Tony Hollick, Joe Jenkins, William John, Michelle Jones, Arjen Kamphius, Henri Kluytmans, Eugene Leitl, Michael Lorrey, mark@unicorn.com, Peter C. McCluskey, Erik Moeller, J. R. Molloy, Max More, Bryan Moss, Harvey Newstrom, Michael Nielsen, John S. Novak III, Dalibor van den Otter, David Pearce, pilgrim@cyberdude.com, Thom Quinn, Anders Sandberg, Wesley R. Schwein, Shakehip@aol.com, Allen Smith, Geoff Smith, Randy Smith, Dennis Stevens, Derek Strong, Remi Sussan, Natasha Vita-More, Michael Wiik, Eliezer Yudkowsky, and zebo@pro-ns.net</p>
<p>Over the years, this FAQ has been updated to provide a substantial account of transhumanism. Extropy Institute (ExI) was a source of information for the first version of the Transhumanist FAQ, version 1.0 in the 1990s. WTA adopted the FAQ in 2001 and Nick Bostrom and James Hughes continued to work on it, with the contributions of close to hundred people from ExI and WTA, including Aleph and Transcedo and the UK Transhumanist Association. New material has been added and many old sections have been substantially reworked. In the preparation of version 2.0, the following people have been especially helpful: Eliezer Yudkowsky, who provided editorial assistance with comments on particular issues of substance; Dale Carrico who proofread the first half of the text; and Michael LaTorra who did the same for the second half; and “Reason” who then went over the whole document again, as did Frank Forman, and Sarah Banks Forman. Useful comments of either substance or form have also been contributed by (in alphabetical order): Michael Anissimov, Samantha Atkins, Milan Cirkovic, José Luis Cordeiro, George Dvorsky, James Hughes, G.E. Jordan, Vasso Kambourelli, Michael LaTorra, Eugen Leitl, Juan Meridalva, Harvey Newstrom, Emlyn O’Reagan, Christine Peterson, Giulio Prisco, Reason, Rafal Smigrodzki, Simon Smith, Mike Treder, and Mark Walker. Many others have over the years offered questions or reflections that have in some way helped shape this document, and even though it is not possible to name you all, your contributions are warmly appreciated.</p>
<p>The Transhumanist FAQ 3.0, as revised by the continued efforts of many transhumanists, will continue to be updated and modified as we develop new knowledge and better ways of accounting for old knowledge which directly and indirectly relate to transhumanism. Our goal is to provide a reliable source of information about transhumanism.</p>
<p>Thank you to all who have contributed in the past and to those who offer new insights to this FAQ!</p>
<div id="table-of-contents">
<h2 class="h1">Transhumanist FAQ<br>
<em class="small">– version 3.0</em></h2>
<h3 class="h2">General</h3>
<ul>
<li><a href="#what-is-transhumanism">What is transhumanism?</a></li>
<li><a href="#what-is-a-posthuman">What is a posthuman?</a></li>
<li><a href="#what-is-a-transhuman">What is a transhuman?</a></li>
</ul>
<h3 class="h2">Practicalities</h3>
<ul>
<li><a href="#what-are-the-reasons-to-expect-all-these-changes">What are the reasons to expect all these changes?</a></li>
<li><a href="#wont-these-developments-take-thousands-or-millions-of-years">Won’t these developments take thousands or millions of years?</a></li>
<li><a href="#how-can-i-use-transhumanism-in-my-own-life">How can I use transhumanism in my own life?</a></li>
<li><a href="#what-if-it-doesnt-work">What if it doesn’t work?</a></li>
<li><a href="#how-could-i-become-a-posthuman">How could I become a posthuman?</a></li>
<li><a href="#wont-it-be-boring-to-live-forever-in-a-perfect-world">Won’t it be boring to live forever in a perfect world?</a></li>
<li><a href="#how-can-i-get-involved-and-contribute">How can I get involved and contribute?</a></li>
</ul>
<h3 class="h2">Society and Politics</h3>
<ul>
<li><a href="#will-new-technologies-only-benefit-the-rich-and-powerful">Will new technologies only benefit the rich and powerful?</a></li>
<li><a href="#do-transhumanists-advocate-eugenics">Do transhumanists advocate eugenics?</a></li>
<li><a href="#arent-these-future-technologies-very-risky-could-they-even-cause-our-extinction">Aren’t these future technologies very risky? Could they even cause our extinction?</a></li>
<li><a href="#if-these-technologies-are-so-dangerous-should-they-be-banned">If these technologies are so dangerous, should they be banned?</a></li>
<li><a href="#shouldnt-we-concentrate-on-current-problems">Shouldn’t we concentrate on current problems?</a></li>
<li><a href="#will-extended-life-worsen-overpopulation-problems">Will extended life worsen overpopulation problems?</a></li>
<li><a href="#is-there-any-ethical-standard">Is there any ethical standard…</a></li>
<li><a href="#what-kind-of-society-would-posthumans-live-in">What kind of society would posthumans live in?</a></li>
<li><a href="#will-posthumans-or-superintelligent-machines-pose-a-threat-to-humans-who-arent-augmented">Will posthumans or superintelligent machines pose a threat to humans who aren’t augmented?</a></li>
</ul>
<h3 class="h2">Technologies and Projections</h3>
<ul>
<li><a href="#biotechnology-genetic-engineering-stem-cells-and-cloning">Biotechnology, genetic engineering, stem cells, and cloning</a></li>
<li><a href="#what-is-molecular-nanotechnology">What is molecular nanotechnology?</a></li>
<li><a href="#what-is-superintelligence">What is super­intelligence?</a></li>
<li><a href="#what-is-virtual-reality">What is virtual reality?</a></li>
<li><a href="#what-is-cryonics-isnt-the-probability-of-success-too-small">What is cryonics? Isn’t the probability of success too small?</a></li>
<li><a href="#what-is-uploading">What is uploading?</a></li>
<li><a href="#what-is-the-singularity">What is the singularity?</a></li>
</ul>
<h3 class="h2">Transhumanism and Nature</h3>
<ul>
<li><a href="#why-do-transhumanists-want-to-live-longer">Why do transhumanists want to live longer?</a></li>
<li><a href="#isnt-this-tampering-with-nature">Isn’t this tampering with nature?</a></li>
<li><a href="#will-transhuman-technologies-make-us-inhuman">Will transhuman technologies make us inhuman?</a></li>
<li><a href="#isnt-death-part-of-the-natural-order-of-things">Isn’t death part of the natural order of things?</a></li>
<li><a href="#are-transhumanist-technologies-environmentally-sound">Are transhumanist technologies environmentally sound?</a></li>
</ul>
<h3 class="h2">Transhumanism as a Philosophical and Cultural Viewpoint</h3>
<ul>
<li><a href="#what-are-the-philosophical-and-cultural-antecedents-of-transhumanism">What are the philosophical and cultural antecedents of transhumanism?</a></li>
<li><a href="#what-currents-are-there-within-transhumanism">What currents are there within transhumanism?</a></li>
<li><a href="#how-does-transhumanism-relate-to-religion">How does transhumanism relate to religion?</a></li>
<li><a href="#wont-things-like-uploading-cryonics-and-ai-fail">Won’t things like uploading, cryonics, and AI fail…</a></li>
<li><a href="#what-kind-of-transhumanist-art-is-there">What kind of transhumanist art is there?</a></li>
</ul>
<p>The Transhumanist FAQ was conceived as an attempt to develop a broadly based consensus articulation of the basics of responsible transhumanism. The aim was a text that could serve both as a guide to those new to the field and as a reference work for more seasoned participants.</p>
</div>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
<h2 class="h1" id="general"><a href="#general">General</a></h2>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="what-is-transhumanism"><a href="#what-is-transhumanism">What is transhumanism?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p><a href="#introduction">See the introduction.</a></p>
</div>
</div>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="what-is-a-posthuman"><a href="#what-is-a-posthuman">What is a posthuman?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>It is sometimes useful to talk about possible future beings whose basic capacities so radically exceed those of present humans as to be no longer unambiguously human by our current standards. The standard word for such beings is “posthuman”. (Care must be taken to avoid misinter­pretation. “Posthuman” does not denote just anything that happens to come after the human era, nor does it have anything to do with the “posthumous”. In particular, it does not imply that there are no humans anymore.)</p>
<p>Many transhumanists wish to follow life paths which would, sooner or later, require growing into posthuman persons: they yearn to reach intellectual heights as far above any current human genius as humans are above other primates; to be resistant to disease and impervious to aging; to have unlimited youth and vigor; to exercise control over their own desires, moods, and mental states; to be able to avoid feeling tired, hateful, or irritated about petty things; to have an increased capacity for pleasure, love, artistic appreciation, and serenity; to experience novel states of consciousness that current human brains cannot access. It seems likely that the simple fact of living an indefinitely long, healthy, active life would take anyone to posthumanity if they went on accumulating memories, skills, and intelligence.</p>
<p>Posthumans could be completely synthetic artificial intelligences, or they could be enhanced uploads (see <a href="#what-is-uploading">“What is uploading?”</a>), or they could be the result of making many smaller but cumulatively profound augmentations to a biological human. The latter alternative would probably require either the redesign of the human organism using advanced nanotechnology or its radical enhancement using some combination of technologies such as genetic engineering, psycho­pharmacology, anti-aging therapies, neural interfaces, advanced information management tools, memory enhancing drugs, wearable computers, and cognitive techniques.</p>
<p>Some authors write as though simply by changing our self-conception, we have become or could become posthuman. This is a confusion or corruption of the original meaning of the term. The changes required to make us posthuman are too profound to be achievable by merely altering some aspect of psychological theory or the way we think about ourselves. Radical technological modifications to our brains and bodies are needed.</p>
<p>It is difficult for us to imagine what it would be like to be a posthuman person. Posthumans may have experiences and concerns that we cannot fathom, thoughts that cannot fit into the three-pound lumps of neural tissue that we use for thinking. Some posthumans may find it advantageous to jettison their bodies altogether and live as information patterns on vast super-fast computer networks. Their minds may be not only more powerful than ours but may also employ different cognitive architectures or include new sensory modalities that enable greater participation in their virtual reality settings. Posthuman minds might be able to share memories and experiences directly, greatly increasing the efficiency, quality, and modes in which posthumans could communicate with each other. The boundaries between posthuman minds may not be as sharply defined as those between humans.</p>
<p>Posthumans might shape themselves and their environment in so many new and profound ways that speculations about the detailed features of posthumans and the posthuman world are likely to fail.</p>
</div>
</div>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="what-is-a-transhuman"><a href="#what-is-a-transhuman">What is a transhuman?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>In its contemporary usage, “transhuman” refers to an intermediary form between the human and the posthuman (see <a href="#what-is-a-posthuman">“What is a posthuman?”</a>). One might ask, given that our current use of e.g. medicine and information technology enable us to routinely do many things that would have astonished humans living in ancient times, whether we are not already transhuman? The question is a provocative one, but ultimately not very meaningful; the concept of the transhuman is too vague for there to be a definite answer.</p>
<p>A transhumanist is simply someone who advocates transhumanism (see <a href="#what-is-transhumanism">“What is transhumanism?”</a>). It is a common error for reporters and other writers to say that transhumanists “claim to be transhuman” or “call themselves transhuman”. To adopt a philosophy which says that someday everyone ought to have the chance to grow beyond present human limits is clearly not to say that one is better or somehow currently “more advanced” than one’s fellow humans.</p>
<p>The etymology of the term “transhuman” goes back to the futurist FM-2030 (also known as F. M. Estfandiary), who introduced it as shorthand for “transitional human”. Calling transhumans the “earliest manifestation of new evolutionary beings,” FM maintained that signs of transhumanity included prostheses, plastic surgery, intensive use of tele­communications, a cosmopolitan outlook and a globetrotting lifestyle, androgyny, mediated reproduction (such as in vitro fertilization), absence of religious beliefs, and a rejection of traditional family values. However, FM’s diagnostics are of dubious validity. It is unclear why anybody who has had enhancement body parts or a nomadic lifestyle is any closer to becoming a posthuman than the rest of us; nor, of course, are such persons necessarily more admirable or morally commendable than others. In fact, it is perfectly possible to be a transhuman – or, for that matter, a transhumanist – and still embrace most traditional values and principles of personal conduct.</p>
</div>
</div>
<h4>References:</h4>
<ul>
<li>FM-2030, <em>Are You a Transhuman?</em> (New York: Warner Books, 1989)</li>
</ul>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<h2 class="h1" id="practicalities"><a href="#practicalities">Practicalities</a></h2>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="what-are-the-reasons-to-expect-all-these-changes"><a href="#what-are-the-reasons-to-expect-all-these-changes">What are the reasons to expect all these changes?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>Take a look around. Compare what you see with what you would have seen only fifty years ago. It is not an especially bold conjecture that the next 50 years will see at least as much change and that the state of technology in the mid-21st century will be quite wondrous by present standards. The conservative projection, which assumes only that progress continues in the same gradual way it has since the 17th century, would imply that we should expect to see dramatic developments over the coming decades.</p>
<p>This expectation is reinforced when one considers that many crucial areas seem poised for critical breakthroughs. The World-Wide Web is beginning to link the world’s people, adding a new global layer to human society where information is supreme. The Human Genome Project has been completed, and the study of the functional roles of our genes (functional genomics) is proceeding rapidly. Techniques for using this genetic information to modify adult organisms or the germ-line are being developed. The performance of computers doubles every 18 months and will approach the computational power of a human brain in the foreseeable future. Pharmaceutical companies are refining drugs that will enable us to regulate mood and aspects of personality with few side effects. Many transhumanist aims can be pursued with present technologies. Can there be much doubt that, barring a civilization-destroying cataclysm, technological progress will give us much more radical options in the future? (See also <a href="#wont-these-developments-take-thousands-or-millions-of-years">“Won’t these developments take thousands or millions of years?”</a>)</p>
<p>Molecular manufacturing has the potential to transform the human condition. Is it a feasible technology? Eric Drexler and others have showed in detail how machine-phase nanotechnology is consistent with physical laws and have outlined several routes by which it could be developed (see <a href="#what-is-molecular-nanotechnology">“What is molecular nanotechnology?”</a>). Molecular manufacturing might seem incredible, maybe because the eventual consequences seem too overwhelming, but nanotechnology experts point out that there currently exists no published technical critique of Drexler’s arguments. More than ten years after the publication of Nanosystems, nobody has yet been able to point to any significant error in the calculations. Meanwhile, investment in the development of nanotechnology, already billions of dollars annually worldwide, is growing every year, and at least the less visionary aspects of nanotechnology have already become mainstream.</p>
<p>There are many independent methods and technologies that can enable humans to become posthuman. There is uncertainty about which technologies will be perfected first, and we have a choice about which methods to use. But provided civilization continues to prosper, it seems almost inevitable that humans will sooner or later have the option of becoming posthuman persons. And, unless forcibly prevented, many will choose to explore that option.</p>
</div>
</div>
<h4>References:</h4>
<ul>
<li>K. Eric Drexler, <em>Nanosystems: Molecular Machinery, Manufacturing, and Computation</em>, (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1992)</li>
</ul>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="wont-these-developments-take-thousands-or-millions-of-years"><a href="#wont-these-developments-take-thousands-or-millions-of-years">Won’t these developments take thousands or millions of years?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>It is often very hard to predict how long a certain technological development will take. The moon landing happened sooner than most people had expected, but fusion energy still eludes us after half a century of anticipation. The difficulty in forecasting the timing lies partly in the possibility of unexpected technical obstacles and partly in the fact that the rate of progress depends on levels of funding, which in turn depends on hard-to-predict economic and political factors. Therefore, while one can in many cases give good grounds for thinking that a technology will eventually be developed, one can usually only make informed guesses about how long it will take.</p>
<p>The vast majority of transhumanists think that super­intelligence and nanotechnology will both be developed in less than a hundred years, and many predict that it will happen well within the first third of this century. (Some of the reasons for holding these opinions are outlined in the sections about these two technologies.) Once there is both nanotechnology and super­intelligence, a very wide range of special applications will follow swiftly.</p>
<p>It would be possible to give a long list of examples where people in the past have solemnly declared that something was technologically absolutely impossible:</p>
<blockquote>
<p>The secrets of flight will not be mastered within our lifetime – not within a thousand years.</p>
– Wilbur Wright (1901)
</blockquote>
<p>or socially irrelevant:</p>
<blockquote>
<p>There is no reason why anyone would want a computer in their home.</p>
– Ken Olsen, President, Chairman and Founder of Digital Equipment Corporation (1977)
</blockquote>
<p>– only to see it happen few years later. However, one could give an equally long list of cases of predicted breakthroughs that failed to occur. The question cannot be settled by enumerating historical parallels.</p>
<p>A better strategy is to look directly at what a careful analysis of the underlying physical constraints and engineering constraints might reveal. In the case of the most crucial future technologies – super­intelligence and molecular manufacturing – such analyses have been done. Many experts believe that these will likely be achieved within the first several decades of the 21st century. Other experts think it will take much longer. There seems to be more disagreement about the feasibility and time-frame of super­intelligence than of nanotechnology.</p>
<p>Another way of forming a view of where we are headed is by looking at trends. At least since the late 19th century, science and technology, as measured by a wide range of indicators, have doubled about every 15 years (Price 1986). Extrapolating this exponential rate of progress, one is led to expect to see dramatic changes in the relatively near future. It would require an abrupt reversal of current trends, an unexpected deceleration, in order for the changes that many transhumanists foresee not to happen within the 21st century.</p>
</div>
</div>
<h4>References:</h4>
<ul>
<li>The Foresight Institute, <a href="https://web.archive.org/web/20140227092747/http://www.foresight.org/news/negativeComments.html">“Erroneous Predictions and Negative Comments Concerning Scientific and Technological Developments”</a> (2002)</li>
<li>Derek J. de Solla Price, <em>Little Science, Big Science …and Beyond</em> (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986)</li>
</ul>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="how-can-i-use-transhumanism-in-my-own-life"><a href="#how-can-i-use-transhumanism-in-my-own-life">How can I use transhumanism in my own life?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>While transhumanism has been known to cross over with academic agendas, ethical philosophies, political causes, and artistic movements, transhumanism is not a lifestyle, a religion, or a self-help guide. Transhumanism can’t tell you what kind of music to listen to, which hobbies to pursue, whom to marry or how to live your life, any more than, say, being a member of Amnesty International or studying molecular biology could tell you these things.</p>
<p>Depending on your situation and your needs, you might or might not find some of the currently available human modification or enhancement options useful. Some of these are commonplace – exercise, healthy diet, relaxation techniques, time management, study skills, information technology, coffee or tea (as stimulants), education, and nutritional supplements (such as vitamins, minerals, fatty acids, or hormones). Others you might not have thought of, such as getting a cryonic suspension contract (see <a href="#what-is-cryonics-isnt-the-probability-of-success-too-small">“What is cryonics? Isn’t the probability of success too small?”</a>), or chewing nicotine gum for its nootropic effects. Still others – for instance pharmacological mood drugs or sex reassignment surgery – are suitable only for people who have special difficulties or needs.</p>
<p>If you want to learn more about transhumanist topics, meet like-minded individuals, and participate in some way the transhumanist effort, see <a href="#how-can-i-get-involved-and-contribute">“How can I get involved and contribute?”</a></p>
</div>
</div>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="what-if-it-doesnt-work"><a href="#what-if-it-doesnt-work">What if it doesn’t work?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>Success in the transhumanist endeavor is not an all-or-nothing matter. There is no “it” that everything hinges on. Instead, there are many incremental processes at play, which may work better or worse, faster or more slowly. Even if we can’t cure all diseases, we will cure many. Even if we don’t get immortality, we can have healthier lives. Even if we can’t freeze whole bodies and revive them, we can learn how to store organs for transplantation. Even if we don’t solve world hunger, we can feed a lot of people. With many potentially transforming technologies already available and others in the pipeline, it is clear that there will be a large scope for human augmentation. The more powerful transhuman technologies, such as machine-phase nanotechnology and super­intelligence, can be reached through several independent paths. Should we find one path to be blocked, we can try another one. The multiplicity of routes adds to the probability that our journey will not come to a premature halt.</p>
<p>There are ways to fail completely, namely if we succumb to an existential disaster (see <a href="#arent-these-future-technologies-very-risky-could-they-even-cause-our-extinction">“Aren’t these future technologies very risky? Could they even cause our extinction?”</a>. Efforts to reduce existential risks are therefore a top priority.</p>
</div>
</div>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="how-could-i-become-a-posthuman"><a href="#how-could-i-become-a-posthuman">How could I become a posthuman?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>At present, there is no manner by which any human can become a posthuman. This is the primary reason for the strong interest in life extension and cryonics among transhumanists. Those of us who live long enough to witness currently foreseeable technologies come to fruition may get the chance to become posthuman. Although there are no guarantees of success, there are some things that can be done on an individual level that will improve the odds a bit:</p>
<ol>
<li>Live healthily and avoid unnecessary risks (diet, exercise, etc.);</li>
<li>Sign up for cryonics;</li>
<li>Keep abreast of current research and save some money so that you can afford future life-extension treatments when they become available;</li>
<li>Support the development of transhuman technologies through donations, advocacy, investment, or choosing a career in the field; work to make access more universal and to make the world safer from existential risks (see <a href="#arent-these-future-technologies-very-risky-could-they-even-cause-our-extinction">“Aren’t these future technologies very risky? Could they even cause our extinction?”</a>);</li>
<li>Join others to help promote transhumanism.</li>
</ol>
<p>Meanwhile, we can enjoy and make the most of the opportunities that exist today for living worthwhile and meaningful lives. If we compare our current lot with that of our historical ancestors, most (at least those of us who don’t live in the least developed countries) will find that the material circumstances for human flourishing are the best they have ever been. In addition, we possess an unprecedented accumulation of cultural and intellectual treasures whereby we can enrich our experiences and broaden our horizons.</p>
</div>
</div>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="wont-it-be-boring-to-live-forever-in-a-perfect-world"><a href="#wont-it-be-boring-to-live-forever-in-a-perfect-world">Won’t it be boring to live forever in a perfect world?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>Why not try it and see?</p>
<p>“Perfection” is a vague and treacherous word. There is considerable disagreement among transhumanists about what kind of perfection is attainable and desirable, either in theory or in practice. It is probably wiser to speak of improving the world, rather than making it “perfect”. Would it be boring to live for an indefinitely long time in a greatly improved world? The world could surely be improved over the way it is now, including becoming less boring. If you got rid of the pain and stress associated with, say, filling out annual tax returns, people would probably not sit around afterward saying: “Life feels meaningless now that I no longer have income tax forms to fill out.”</p>
<p>Admittedly, material improvements to the environment may not, in themselves, be sufficient to bring about lasting happiness. If your accustomed fare is bread and water, then a box of cookies can be a feast. But if every night you eat out at fancy restaurants, such fine fare will soon seem ordinary and normal; and any lesser feast, such as a box of cookies, would be insulting by comparison. Some cognitive scientists speculate that we each have a “set point” of happiness, to which we soon return regardless of changes in the environment. There may be considerable truth to the folk wisdom that an expensive new car does not make you happier (or rather, it makes you happier, but only temporarily). In some ways, human minds and brains are just not designed to be happy. Fortunately, there are several potential viewpoints from which to go about addressing this challenge.</p>
<p>Apes engage in activities that we, as humans, would find repetitive and dull. In the course of becoming smarter, we have become bored by things that would have interested our ancestors. But at the same time we have opened up a vast new space of possibilities for having fun – and the new space is much larger than the previous one. Humans are not simply apes who can obtain more bananas using our intelligence as a tool. Our intelligence enables us to desire new things, such as art, science, and mathematics. If at any point in your indefinitely long life you become bored with the greatly improved world, it may only indicate that the time has come to bump up your intelligence another increment.</p>
<p>If the human brain has a “set point” of happiness to which it returns, maybe this is a design flaw and should be fixed – one of those things that we will end up defining as human, but not humane. It would probably be unwise to eliminate boredom entirely, since boredom can serve to prevent us from wasting too much time on monotonous and meaningless activities. But if we’re doing new things, learning, growing more intelligent, and we still aren’t happy, for no better reason than that our cognitive architecture is badly designed, then perhaps it is time to redesign it. Present clinical mood-drugs are crude, but nonetheless they can sometimes restore interest and enthusiasm for life – sometimes tiredness and despair has no interesting reason behind it and is simply an imbalance of brain chemistry. Only by compartmentalizing our thinking to a high degree can we imagine a world where there is mature molecular nanotechnology and superhuman artificial intelligence, but the means are still lacking to control the brain circuitry of boredom. Fundamentally, there is no reason why pleasure, excitement, profound well-being and simple joy at being alive could not become the natural, default state of mind for all who desire it.</p>
<p>Ed Regis (1990, p. 97) suggests the following points also be considered:</p>
<ol>
<li>Ordinary life is sometimes boring. So what?</li>
<li>Eternal life will be as boring or as exciting as you make it.</li>
<li>Is being dead more exciting?</li>
<li>If eternal life becomes boring, you will have the option of ending it at any time.</li>
</ol>
<p>Transhumanism is not about a fancier car, more money, or clever gadgetry, even though this is what the media presents to us as “science” and “advanced technology”; transhumanism is about genuine changes to the human condition, including increased intelligence and minds better suited to the achievement of happiness.</p>
</div>
</div>
<h4>References:</h4>
<ul>
<li>David Pearce, <a href="https://www.hedweb.com/">The Hedonistic Imperative</a> (2003)</li>
<li>Ed Regis, <em>Great Mambo Chicken and the Transhuman Condition</em> (New York: Penguin Books, 1990)</li>
</ul>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="how-can-i-get-involved-and-contribute"><a href="#how-can-i-get-involved-and-contribute">How can I get involved and contribute?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>You can join Humanity+. The Humanity+ is a nonprofit, democratic membership organization that works to promote discussion of possibilities for the radical improvement of human capacities using technology, as well as of the ethical issues and risks involved in technological developments. It was founded in 1998 as an umbrella organization to publicize transhumanist ideas and to seek academic acceptance of transhumanism as a philosophical and cultural movement. Humanity+ organizes conferences, publishes H+ Magazine, (did published an academic journal), issues press statements, and coordinates student campus chapters and local transhumanist groups around the world. To find out about current projects and upcoming events, and to become a member, please visit the Humanity+ website.</p>
<p>Humanity+ has been growing since its inception and especially rapidly in the last couple of years, but the task before us is both momentous and mountainous. Your help is needed. There are myriad ways to contribute – organizing or participating in a local discussion group, writing articles or letters to the editor, making a financial contribution, spreading the word to friends and acquaintances, volunteering your skills, translating key documents into other languages, linking to Humanity+ from your website, attending conferences and sharing your ideas, directing your research or creative activity towards transhumanist themes, to name but a few.</p>
<p>If you want to study transhumanist ideas in more detail, you can find some syllabi and reading lists on the website to get you started. If you want to exchange ideas with others, or just listen in to ongoing conversations, you may want to join one of the mailing lists and newsgroups maintained by Humanity+.</p>
<p>The coming technological transitions may be the most important challenge that humanity will ever face. The entire future of intelligent life on Earth may depend on how we handle it. If we do the right things, a wonderful posthuman future with limitless opportunities for growth and flourishing may lie ahead. If we handle it badly, intelligent life might go extinct. Don’t you want to take part and attempt to make a difference for the better?</p>
</div>
</div>
<h4>References:</h4>
<ul>
<li><a href="https://www.humanityplus.org/">Humanity+</a> (From this site, links to local groups and affiliated organizations can also be found.)</li>
</ul>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<h2 class="h1" id="society-and-politics"><a href="#society-and-politics">Society and Politics</a></h2>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="will-new-technologies-only-benefit-the-rich-and-powerful"><a href="#will-new-technologies-only-benefit-the-rich-and-powerful">Will new technologies only benefit the rich and powerful?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>One could make the case that the average citizen of a developed country today has a higher standard of living than any king five hundred years ago. The king might have had a court orchestra, but you can afford a CD player that lets you to listen to the best musicians any time you want. When the king got pneumonia he might well die, but you can take antibiotics. The king might have a carriage with six white horses, but you can have a car that is faster and more comfortable. And you likely have television, Internet access, and a shower with warm water; you can talk with relatives who live in a different country over the phone; and you know more about the Earth, nature, and the cosmos than any medieval monarch.</p>
<p>The typical pattern with new technologies is that they become cheaper as time goes by. In the medical field, for example, experimental procedures are usually available only to research subjects and the very rich. As these procedures become routine, costs fall and more people can afford them. Even in the poorest countries, millions of people have benefited from vaccines and penicillin. In the field of consumer electronics, the price of computers and other devices that were cutting-edge only a couple of years ago drops precipitously as new models are introduced.</p>
<p>It is clear that everybody can benefit greatly from improved technology. Initially, however, the greatest advantages will go to those who have the resources, the skills, and the willingness to learn to use new tools. One can speculate that some technologies may cause social inequalities to widen. For example, if some form of intelligence amplification becomes available, it may at first be so expensive that only the wealthiest can afford it. The same could happen when we learn how to genetically enhance our children. Those who are already well off would become smarter and make even more money. This phenomenon is not new. Rich parents send their kids to better schools and provide them with resources such as personal connections and information technology that may not be available to the less privileged. Such advantages lead to greater earnings later in life and serve to increase social inequalities.</p>
<p>Trying to ban technological innovation on these grounds, however, would be misguided. If a society judges existing inequalities to be unacceptable, a wiser remedy would be progressive taxation and the provision of community-funded services such as education, IT access in public libraries, genetic enhancements covered by social security, and so forth. Economic and technological progress is not a zero sum game; it’s a positive sum game. Technological progress does not solve the hard old political problem of what degree of income redistribution is desirable, but it can greatly increase the size of the pie that is to be divided.</p>
</div>
</div>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="do-transhumanists-advocate-eugenics"><a href="#do-transhumanists-advocate-eugenics">Do transhumanists advocate eugenics?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>Eugenics in the narrow sense refers to the pre-WWII movement in Europe and the United States to involuntarily sterilize the “genetically unfit” and encourage breeding of the genetically advantaged. These ideas are entirely contrary to the tolerant humanistic and scientific tenets of transhumanism. In addition to condemning the coercion involved in such policies, transhumanists strongly reject the racialist and classist assumptions on which they were based, along with the notion that eugenic improvements could be accomplished in a practically meaningful timeframe through selective human breeding.</p>
<p>Transhumanists uphold the principles of bodily autonomy and procreative liberty. Parents must be allowed to choose for themselves whether to reproduce, how to reproduce, and what technological methods they use in their reproduction. The use of genetic medicine or embryonic screening to increase the probability of a healthy, happy, and multiply talented child is a responsible and justifiable application of parental reproductive freedom.</p>
<p>Beyond this, one can argue that parents have a moral responsibility to make use of these methods, assuming they are safe and effective. Just as it would be wrong for parents to fail in their duty to procure the best available medical care for their sick child, it would be wrong not to take reasonable precautions to ensure that a child-to-be will be as healthy as possible. This, however, is a moral judgment that is best left to individual conscience rather than imposed by law. Only in extreme and unusual cases might state infringement of procreative liberty be justified. If, for example, a would-be parent wished to undertake a genetic modification that would be clearly harmful to the child or would drastically curtail its options in life, then this prospective parent should be prevented by law from doing so. This case is analogous to the state taking custody of a child in situations of gross parental neglect or child abuse.</p>
<p>This defense of procreative liberty is compatible with the view that states and charities can subsidize public health, prenatal care, genetic counseling, contraception, abortion, and genetic therapies so that parents can make free and informed reproductive decisions that result in fewer disabilities in the next generation. Some disability activists would call these policies eugenic, but society may have a legitimate interest in whether children are born healthy or disabled, leading it to subsidize the birth of healthy children, without actually outlawing or imposing particular genetic modifications.</p>
<p>When discussing the morality of genetic enhancements, it is useful to be aware of the distinction between enhancements that are intrinsically beneficial to the child or society on the one hand, and, on the other, enhancements that provide a merely positional advantage to the child. For example, health, cognitive abilities, and emotional well-being are valued by most people for their own sake. It is simply nice to be healthy, happy and to be able to think well, quite independently of any other advantages that come from possessing these attributes. By contrast, traits such as attractiveness, athletic prowess, height, and assertiveness seem to confer benefits that are mostly positional, i.e. they benefit a person by making her more competitive (e.g. in sports or as a potential mate), at the expense of those with whom she will compete, who suffer a corresponding disadvantage from her enhancement. Enhancements that have only positional advantages ought to be de-emphasized, while enhancements that create net benefits ought to be encouraged.</p>
<p>It is sometimes claimed that the use of germinal choice technologies would lead to an undesirable uniformity of the population. Some degree of uniformity is desirable and expected if we are able to make everyone congenitally healthy, strong, intelligent, and attractive. Few would argue that we should preserve cystic fibrosis because of its contribution to diversity. But other kinds of diversity are sure to flourish in a society with germinal choice, especially once adults are able to adapt their own bodies according to their own aesthetic tastes. Presumably most Asian parents will still choose to have children with Asian features, and if some parents choose genes that encourage athleticism, others may choose genes that correlate with musical ability.</p>
<p>It is unlikely that germ-line genetic enhancements will ever have a large impact on the world. It will take a minimum of forty or fifty years for the requisite technologies to be developed, tested, and widely applied and for a significant number of enhanced individuals to be born and reach adulthood. Before this happens, more powerful and direct methods for individuals to enhance themselves will probably be available, based on nanomedicine, artificial intelligence, uploading, or somatic gene therapy. (Traditional eugenics, based on selecting who is allowed to reproduce, would have even less prospect of avoiding preemptive obsolescence, as it would take many generations to deliver its purported improvements.)</p>
</div>
</div>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="arent-these-future-technologies-very-risky-could-they-even-cause-our-extinction"><a href="#arent-these-future-technologies-very-risky-could-they-even-cause-our-extinction">Aren’t these future technologies very risky? Could they even cause our extinction?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>Yes, and this implies an urgent need to analyze the risks before they materialize and to take steps to reduce them. Biotechnology, nanotechnology, and artificial intelligence pose especially serious risks of accidents and abuse. (See also <a href="#if-these-technologies-are-so-dangerous-should-they-be-banned">“If these technologies are so dangerous, should they be banned?”</a>)</p>
<p>One can distinguish between, on the one hand, endurable or limited hazards, such as car crashes, nuclear reactor meltdowns, carcinogenic pollutants in the atmosphere, floods, volcano eruptions, and so forth, and, on the other hand, existential risks – events that would cause the extinction of intelligent life or permanently and drastically cripple its potential. While endurable or limited risks can be serious – and may indeed be fatal to the people immediately exposed – they are recoverable; they do not destroy the long-term prospects of humanity as a whole. Humanity has long experience with endurable risks and a variety of institutional and technological mechanisms have been employed to reduce their incidence. Existential risks are a different kind of beast. For most of human history, there were no significant existential risks, or at least none that our ancestors could do anything about. By definition, of course, no existential disaster has yet happened. As a species we may therefore be less well prepared to understand and manage this new kind of risk. Furthermore, the reduction of existential risk is a global public good (everybody by necessity benefits from such safety measures, whether or not they contribute to their development), creating a potential free-rider problem, i.e. a lack of sufficient selfish incentives for people to make sacrifices to reduce an existential risk. Transhumanists therefore recognize a moral duty to promote efforts to reduce existential risks.</p>
<p>The gravest existential risks facing us in the coming decades will be of our own making. These include:</p>
<p>Destructive uses of nanotechnology. The accidental release of a self-replicating nanobot into the environment, where it would proceed to destroy the entire biosphere, is known as the “gray goo scenario”. Since molecular nanotechnology will make use of positional assembly to create non-biological structures and to open new chemical reaction pathways, there is no reason to suppose that the ecological checks and balances that limit the proliferation of organic self-replicators would also contain nano-replicators. Yet, while gray goo is certainly a legitimate concern, relatively simple engineering safeguards have been described that would make the probability of such a mishap almost arbitrarily small (Foresight 2002). Much more serious is the threat posed by nanobots deliberately designed to be destructive. A terrorist group or even a lone psychopath, having obtained access to this technology, could do extensive damage or even annihilate life on earth unless effective defensive technologies had been developed beforehand (Center for Responsible Nanotechnology 2003). An unstable arms race between nanotechnic states could also result in our eventual demise (Gubrud 2000). Anti-proliferation efforts will be complicated by the fact that nanotechnology does not require difficult-to-obtain raw materials or large manufacturing plants, and by the dual-use functionality of many of the basic components of destructive nanomachinery. While a nanotechnic defense system (which would act as a global immune system capable of identifying and neutralizing rogue replicators) appears to be possible in principle, it could turn out to be more difficult to construct than a simple destructive replicator. This could create a window of global vulnerability between the potential creation of dangerous replicators and the development of an effective immune system. It is critical that nano-assemblers do not fall into the wrong hands during this period.</p>
<p>Biological warfare. Progress in genetic engineering will lead not only to improvements in medicine but also to the capability to create more effective bioweapons. It is chilling to consider what would have happened if HIV had been as contagious as the virus that causes the common cold. Engineering such microbes might soon become possible for increasing numbers of people. If the RNA sequence of a virus is posted on the Internet, then anybody with some basic expertise and access to a lab will be able to synthesize the actual virus from this description. A demonstration of this possibility was offered by a small team of researchers from New York University at Stony Brook in 2002, who synthesized the polio virus (whose genetic sequence is on the Internet) from scratch and injected it into mice who subsequently became paralyzed and died.</p>
<p>Artificial intelligence. No threat to human existence is posed by today’s AI systems or their near-term successors. But if and when super­intelligence is created, it will be of paramount importance that it be endowed with human-friendly values. An imprudently or maliciously designed super­intelligence, with goals amounting to indifference or hostility to human welfare, could cause our extinction. Another concern is that the first super­intelligence, which may become very powerful because of its superior planning ability and because of the technologies it could swiftly develop, would be built to serve only a single person or a small group (such as its programmers or the corporation that commissioned it). While this scenario may not entail the extinction of literally all intelligent life, it nevertheless constitutes an existential risk because the future that would result would be one in which a great part of humanity’s potential had been permanently destroyed and in which at most a tiny fraction of all humans would get to enjoy the benefits of posthumanity. (See also <a href="#will-posthumans-or-superintelligent-machines-pose-a-threat-to-humans-who-arent-augmented">“Will posthumans or superintelligent machines pose a threat to humans who aren’t augmented?”</a>)</p>
<p>Nuclear war. Today’s nuclear arsenals are probably not sufficient to cause the extinction of all humans, but future arms races could result in even larger build-ups. It is also conceivable that an all-out nuclear war would lead to the collapse of modern civilization, and it is not completely certain that the survivors would succeed in rebuilding a civilization capable of sustaining growth and technological development.</p>
<p>Something unknown. All the above risks were unknown a century ago and several of them have only become clearly understood in the past two decades. It is possible that there are future threats of which we haven’t yet become aware.</p>
<p>For a more extensive discussion of these and many other existential risks, see Bostrom (2002).</p>
<p>Evaluating the total probability that some existential disaster will do us in before we get the opportunity to become posthuman can be done by various direct or indirect methods. Although any estimate inevitably includes a large subjective factor, it seems that to set the probability to less than 20% would be unduly optimistic, and the best estimate may be considerably higher. But depending on the actions we take, this figure can be raised or lowered.</p>
</div>
</div>
<h4>References:</h4>
<ul>
<li>Nick Bostrom, <a href="https://www.nickbostrom.com/existential/risks.html">“Existential Risks: Analyzing Human Extinction Scenarios and Related Hazards”</a>, <em>Journal of Evolution and Technology</em> Vol. 9 (2002)</li>
<li>Center for Responsible Nanotechnology, <a href="http://crnano.org/dangers.htm">“Dangers of Molecular Manufacturing”</a> (2003)</li>
<li>Foresight Institute, <a href="https://web.archive.org/web/20210506004854/https://foresight.org/guidelines/current.html">“Foresight Guidelines on Molecular Nanotechnology, version 3.7”</a> (2000)</li>
<li>Mark Avrum Gubrud, <a href="https://web.archive.org/web/20210506013931/http://www.foresight.org/Conferences/MNT05/Papers/Gubrud/index.html">“Nanotechnology and International Security”</a>, Fifth Foresight Conference on Molecular Nanotechnology (1997)</li>
<li>Eckard Wimmer et al., “Chemical Synthesis of Poliovirus cDNA: Generation of Infectious Virus in the Absence of Natural Template”, <em>Science</em> Vol. 257, No. 5583, (2002), 1016–1018</li>
</ul>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="if-these-technologies-are-so-dangerous-should-they-be-banned"><a href="#if-these-technologies-are-so-dangerous-should-they-be-banned">If these technologies are so dangerous, should they be banned?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>What can be done to reduce the risks?</p>
<p>The position that we ought to relinquish research into robotics, genetic engineering, and nanotechnology has been advocated in an article by Bill Joy (2000). Joy argued that some of the future applications of these technologies are so dangerous that research in those fields should be stopped now. Partly because of Joy’s previously technophiliac credentials (he was a software designer and a cofounder of Sun Microsystems), his article, which appeared in Wired magazine, attracted a great deal of attention.</p>
<p>Many of the responses to Joy’s article pointed out that there is no realistic prospect of a worldwide ban on these technologies; that they have enormous potential benefits that we would not want to forgo; that the poorest people may have a higher tolerance for risk in developments that could improve their condition; and that a ban may actually increase the dangers rather than reduce them, both by delaying the development of protective applications of these technologies, and by weakening the position of those who choose to comply with the ban relative to less scrupulous groups who defy it.</p>
<p>A more promising alternative than a blanket ban is differential technological development, in which we would seek to influence the sequence in which technologies developed. On this approach, we would strive to retard the development of harmful technologies and their applications, while accelerating the development of beneficial technologies, especially those that offer protection against the harmful ones. For technologies that have decisive military applications, unless they can be verifiably banned, we may seek to ensure that they are developed at a faster pace in countries we regard as responsible than in those that we see as potential enemies. (Whether a ban is verifiable and enforceable can change over time as a result of developments in the international system or in surveillance technology.)</p>
<p>In the case of nanotechnology, the desirable sequence of development is that nanotech immune systems and other defensive measures be deployed before offensive capabilities become available to many independent powers. Once a technology is shared by many, it becomes extremely hard to prevent further proliferation. In the case of biotechnology, we should seek to promote research into vaccines, anti-viral drugs, protective gear, sensors, and diagnostics, and to delay as long as possible the development and proliferation of biological warfare agents and the means of their weaponization. For artificial intelligence, a serious risk will emerge only when capabilities approach or surpass those of humans. At that point one should seek to promote the development of friendly AI and to prevent unfriendly or unreliable AI systems.</p>
<p>Super­intelligence is an example of a technology that seems especially worth promoting because it can help reduce a broad range of threats. Superintelligent systems could advise us on policy and make the progress curve for nanotechnology steeper, thus shortening the period of vulnerability between the development of dangerous nanoreplicators and the deployment of effective defenses. If we have a choice, it seems preferable that super­intelligence be developed before advanced nanotechnology, as super­intelligence could help reduce the risks of nanotechnology but not vice versa. Other technologies that have wide risk-reducing uses include intelligence augmentation, information technology, and surveillance. These can make us smarter individually and collectively or make enforcement of necessary regulation more feasible. A strong prima facie case therefore exists for pursuing these technologies as vigorously as possible. Needless to say, we should also promote non-technological developments that are beneficial in almost all scenarios, such as peace and international cooperation.</p>
<p>In confronting the hydra of existential, limited and endurable risks glaring at us from the future, it is unlikely that any one silver bullet will provide adequate protection. Instead, an arsenal of countermeasures will be needed so that we can address the various risks on multiple levels.</p>
<p>The first step to tackling a risk is to recognize its existence. More research is needed, and existential risks in particular should be singled out for attention because of their seriousness and because of the special nature of the challenges they pose. Surprisingly little work has been done in this area (but see e.g. Leslie (1996), Bostrom (2002), and Rees (2003) for some preliminary explorations). The strategic dimensions of our choices must be taken into account, given that some of the technologies in questions have important military ramifications. In addition to scholarly studies of the threats and their possible countermeasures, public awareness must be raised to enable a more informed debate of our long-term options.</p>
<p>Some of the lesser existential risks, such as an apocalyptic asteroid impact or the highly speculative scenario involving something like the upsetting of a metastable vacuum state in some future particle accelerator experiment, could be substantially reduced at relatively small expense. Programs to accomplish this – e.g. an early detection system for dangerous near-earth objects on potential collation course with Earth, or the commissioning of advance peer review of planned high-energy physics experiments – are probably cost-effective. However, these lesser risks must not deflect attention from the more serious concern raised by more probable existential disasters (see <a href="#arent-these-future-technologies-very-risky-could-they-even-cause-our-extinction">“Aren’t these future technologies very risky? Could they even cause our extinction?”</a>).</p>
<p>In light of how superabundant the human benefits of technology can ultimately be, it matters less that we obtain all of these benefits in their precisely most optimal form, and more that we obtain them at all. For many practical purposes, it makes sense to adopt the rule of thumb that we should act so as to maximize the probability of an acceptable outcome, one in which we attain some (reasonably broad) realization of our potential; or, to put it in negative terms, that we should act so as to minimize net existential risk.</p>
</div>
</div>
<h4>References:</h4>
<ul>
<li>Nick Bostrom, <a href="https://www.nickbostrom.com/existential/risks.html">“Existential Risks: Analyzing Human Extinction Scenarios and Related Hazards”</a>, <em>Journal of Evolution and Technology</em> Vol. 9 (2002)</li>
<li>Bill Joy, <a href="https://www.wired.com/2000/04/joy-2/">“Why the future doesn’t need us.”</a>. <em>Wired</em> 8:04 (2000)</li>
<li>John Leslie, <em>The End of the World: The Science and Ethics of Human Extinction</em> (London: Routledge, 1996)</li>
<li>Martin Rees, <em>Our Final Hour: A Scientist’s Warning</em> (New York: Basic Books, 2003)</li>
</ul>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="shouldnt-we-concentrate-on-current-problems"><a href="#shouldnt-we-concentrate-on-current-problems">Shouldn’t we concentrate on current problems?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>such as improving the situation of the poor, rather than putting our efforts into planning for the “far” future?</p>
<p>We should do both. Focusing solely on current problems would leave us unprepared for the new challenges that we will encounter.</p>
<p>Many of the technologies and trends that transhumanists discuss are already reality. Biotechnology and information technology have transformed large sectors of our economies. The relevance of transhumanist ethics is manifest in such contemporary issues as stem cell research, genetically modified crops, human genetic therapy, embryo screening, end of life decisions, enhancement medicine, information markets, and research funding priorities. The importance of transhumanist ideas is likely to increase as the opportunities for human enhancement proliferate.</p>
<p>Transhuman technologies will tend to work well together and create synergies with other parts of human society. For example, one important factor in healthy life expectancy is access to good medical care. Improvements in medical care will extend healthy, active lifespan – “healthspan” – and research into healthspan extension is likely to benefit ordinary care. Work on amplifying intelligence has obvious applications in education, decision-making, and communication. Better communications would facilitate trade and understanding between people. As more and more people get access to the Internet and are able to receive satellite radio and television broadcasts, dictators and totalitarian regimes may find it harder to silence voices of dissent and to control the information flow in their populations. And with the Internet and email, people discover they can easily form friendships and business partnerships in foreign countries. A world order characterized by peace, international cooperation, and respect for human rights would much improve the odds that the potentially dangerous applications of some future technologies can be controlled and would also free up resources currently spent on military armaments, some of which could then hopefully be diverted to improving the condition of the poor. Nanotechnological manufacturing promises to be both economically profitable and environmentally sound. Transhumanists do not have a patent solution to achieve these outcomes, any more than anybody else has, but technology has a huge role to play.</p>
<p>An argument can be made that the most efficient way of contributing to making the world better is by participating in the transhumanist project. This is so because the stakes are enormous – humanity’s entire future may depend on how we manage the coming technological transitions – and because relatively few resources are at the present time being devoted to transhumanist efforts. Even one extra person can still make a significant difference here.</p>
</div>
</div>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="will-extended-life-worsen-overpopulation-problems"><a href="#will-extended-life-worsen-overpopulation-problems">Will extended life worsen overpopulation problems?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>Population increase is an issue we would ultimately have to come to grips with even if healthy life-extension were not to happen. Leaving people to die is an unacceptable solution.</p>
<p>A large population should not be viewed simply as a problem. Another way of looking at the same fact is that it means that many persons now enjoy lives that would not have been lived if the population had been smaller. One could ask those who complain about overpopulation exactly which people’s lives they would have preferred should not have been led. Would it really have been better if billions of the world’s people had never existed and if there had been no other people in their place? Of course, this is not to deny that too-rapid population growth can cause crowding, poverty, and the depletion of natural resources. In this sense there can be real problems that need to be tackled.</p>
<p>How many people the Earth can sustain at a comfortable standard of living is a function of technological development (as well as of how resources are distributed). New technologies, from simple improvements in irrigation and management, to better mining techniques and more efficient power generation machinery, to genetically engineered crops, can continue to improve world resource and food output, while at the same time reducing environmental impact and animal suffering.</p>
<p>Environmentalists are right to insist that the status quo is unsustainable. As a matter of physical necessity, things cannot stay as they are today indefinitely, or even for very long. If we continue to use up resources at the current pace, without finding more resources or learning how to use novel kinds of resources, then we will run into serious shortages sometime around the middle of this century. The deep greens have an answer to this: they suggest we turn back the clock and return to an idyllic pre-industrial age to live in sustainable harmony with nature. The problem with this view is that the pre-industrial age was anything but idyllic. It was a life of poverty, misery, disease, heavy manual toil from dawn to dusk, superstitious fears, and cultural parochialism. Nor was it environmentally sound – as witness the deforestation of England and the Mediterranean region, desertification of large parts of the middle east, soil depletion by the Anasazi in the Glen Canyon area, destruction of farm land in ancient Mesopotamia through the accumulation of mineral salts from irrigation, deforestation and consequent soil erosion by the ancient Mexican Mayas, overhunting of big game almost everywhere, and the extinction of the dodo and other big featherless birds in the South Pacific. Furthermore, it is hard to see how more than a few hundred million people could be maintained at a reasonable standard of living with pre-industrial production methods, so some ninety percent of the world population would somehow have to vanish in order to facilitate this nostalgic return.</p>
<p>Transhumanists propose a much more realistic alternative: not to retreat to an imagined past, but to press ahead as intelligently as we can. The environmental problems that technology creates are problems of intermediary, inefficient technology, of placing insufficient political priority on environmental protection as well as of a lack of ecological knowledge. Technologically less advanced industries in the former Soviet-bloc pollute much more than do their advanced Western counterparts. High-tech industry is typically relatively benign. Once we develop molecular nanotechnology, we will not only have clean and efficient manufacturing of almost any commodity, but we will also be able to clean up much of the mess created by today’s crude fabrication methods. This would set a standard for a clean environment that today’s traditional environmentalists could scarcely dream of.</p>
<p>Nanotechnology will also make it cheaper to colonize space. From a cosmic point of view, Earth is an insignificant speck. It has sometimes been suggested that we ought to leave space untouched in its pristine glory. This view is hard to take seriously. Every hour, through entirely natural processes, vast amounts of resources – millions of times more than the sum total of what the human species has consumed throughout its career – are transformed into radioactive substances or wasted as radiation escaping into intergalactic space. Can we not think of some more creative way of using all this matter and energy?</p>
<p>Even with full-blown space colonization, however, population growth can continue to be a problem, and this is so even if we assume that an unlimited number of people could be transported from Earth into space. If the speed of light provides an upper bound on the expansion speed then the amount of resources under human control will grow only polynomially (~ t3). Population, on the other hand, can easily grow exponentially (~ et). If that happens, then, since a factor that grows exponentially will eventually overtake any factor that grows polynomially, average income will ultimately drop to subsistence levels, forcing population growth to slow. How soon this would happen depends primarily on reproduction rates. A change in average life span would not have a big effect. Even vastly improved technology can only postpone this inevitability for a relatively brief time. The only long-term method of assuring continued growth of average income is some form of population control, whether spontaneous or imposed, limiting the number of new persons created per year. This does not mean that population could not grow, only that the growth would have to be polynomial rather than exponential.</p>
<p>Some additional points to consider:</p>
<p>In technologically advanced countries, couples tend to have fewer children, often below the replacement rate. As an empirical generalization, giving people increased rational control over their lives, especially through women’s education and participation in the labor market, causes couples to have fewer children.</p>
<p>If one took seriously the idea of controlling population by limiting life span, why not be more active about it? Why not encourage suicide? Why not execute anyone reaching the age of 75?</p>
<p>If slowing aging were unacceptable because it might lead to there being more people, what about efforts to cure cancer, reduce traffic deaths, or improve worker safety? Why use double standards?</p>
<p>When transhumanists say they want to extend lifespans, what they mean is that they want to extend healthspans. This means that the extra person-years would be productive and would add economic value to society. We can all agree that there would be little point in living an extra ten years in a state of dementia.</p>
<p>The world population growth rate has been declining for several decades. It peaked in 1970 at 2.1%. In 2003, it was 1.2%; and it is expected to fall below 1.0% around 2015. (United Nations 2002). The doomsday predictions of the so-called “Club of Rome” from the early 1970s have consistently turned out to be wrong.</p>
<p>The more people there are, the more brains there will be working to invent new ideas and solutions.</p>
<p>If people can look forward to a longer healthy, active life, they will have a personal stake in the future and will hopefully be more concerned about the long-term consequences of their actions.</p>
</div>
</div>
<h4>References:</h4>
<ul>
<li>United Nations, The World Population Prospects: The 2002 Revision (United Nations: New York, 2002)</li>
</ul>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="is-there-any-ethical-standard"><a href="#is-there-any-ethical-standard">Is there any ethical standard…</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>…by which transhumanists judge “improvement of the human condition”?</p>
<p>Transhumanism is compatible with a variety of ethical systems, and transhumanists themselves hold many different views. Nonetheless, the following seems to constitute a common core of agreement:</p>
<p>According to transhumanists, the human condition has been improved if the conditions of individual humans have been improved. In practice, competent adults are usually the best judges of what is good for themselves. Therefore, transhumanists advocate individual freedom, especially the right for those who so wish to use technology to extend their mental and physical capacities and to improve their control over their own lives.</p>
<p>From this perspective, an improvement to the human condition is a change that gives increased opportunity for individuals to shape themselves and their lives according to their informed wishes. Notice the word “informed”. It is important that people be aware of what they choose between. Education, discussion, public debate, critical thinking, artistic exploration, and, potentially, cognitive enhancers are means that can help people make more informed choices.</p>
<p>Transhumanists hold that people are not disposable. Saving lives (of those who want to live) is ethically important. It would be wrong to unnecessarily let existing people die in order to replace them with some new “better” people. Healthspan-extension and cryonics are therefore high on the transhumanist list of priorities. The transhumanist goal is not to replace existing humans with a new breed of super-beings, but rather to give human beings (those existing today and those who will be born in the future) the option of developing into posthuman persons.</p>
<p>The non-disposability of persons partially accounts for a certain sense of urgency that is common among transhumanists. On average, 150,000 men, women, and children die every day, often in miserable conditions. In order to give as many people as possible the chance of a posthuman existence – or even just a decent human existence – it is paramount that technological development, in at least some fields, is pursued with maximal speed. When it comes to life-extension and its various enabling technologies, a delay of a single week equals one million avoidable premature deaths – a weighty fact which those who argue for bans or moratoria would do well to consider carefully. (The further fact that universal access will likely lag initial availability only adds to the reason for trying to hurry things along.)</p>
<p>Transhumanists reject speciesism, the (human racist) view that moral status is strongly tied to membership in a particular biological species, in our case homo sapiens. What exactly does determine moral status is a matter of debate. Factors such as being a person, being sentient, having the capacity for autonomous moral choice, or perhaps even being a member of the same community as the evaluator, are among the criteria that may combine to determine the degree of somebody’s moral status (Warren 1997). But transhumanists argue that species-identity should be de-emphasized in this context. Transhumanists insist that all beings that can experience pain have some moral status, and that posthuman persons could have at least the same level of moral status as humans have in their current form.</p>
</div>
</div>
<h4>References:</h4>
<ul>
<li>Mary Anne Warren, <em>Moral Status: Obligations to Persons and Other Living Things</em> (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997)</li>
</ul>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="what-kind-of-society-would-posthumans-live-in"><a href="#what-kind-of-society-would-posthumans-live-in">What kind of society would posthumans live in?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>Not enough information is available at the current time to provide a full answer to this question. In part, though, the answer is, “You decide.” The outcome may be influenced by the choices we make now and over the coming decades. In this respect, the situation is the same as in earlier epochs that had no transhuman possibilities: by becoming involved in political struggles against today’s social ills and injustices, we can help make tomorrow’s society better.</p>
<p>Transhumanism does, however, inform us about new constraints, possibilities, and issues, and it highlights numerous important leverage points for intervention, where a small application of resources can make a big long-term difference. For example, one issue that moves into prominence is the challenge of creating a society in which beings with vastly different orders of capabilities (such as posthuman persons and as-yet non-augmented humans) can live happily and peacefully together. Another concern that becomes paramount is the need to build a world order in which dangerous arms races can be prevented and in which the proliferation of weapons of mass destruction can be suppressed or at least delayed until effective defenses have been developed (see <a href="#arent-these-future-technologies-very-risky-could-they-even-cause-our-extinction">“Aren’t these future technologies very risky? Could they even cause our extinction?”</a>).</p>
<p>The ideal social organization may be one that includes the possibility for those who so wish to form independent societies voluntarily secluded from the rest of the world, in order to pursue traditional ways of life or to experiment with new forms of communal living. Achieving an acceptable balance between the rights of such communities for autonomy, on the one hand, and the security concerns of outside entities and the just demands for protection of vulnerable and oppressed individuals inside these communities on the other hand, is a delicate task and a familiar challenge in political philosophy.</p>
<p>What types of society posthumans will live in depends on what types of posthumans eventually develop. One can project various possible developmental paths (see <a href="#what-is-a-posthuman">“What is a posthuman?”</a>) which may result in very different kinds of posthuman, transhuman, and unaugmented human beings, living in very different sorts of societies. In attempting to imagine such a world, we must bear in mind that we are likely to base our expectations on the experiences, desires, and psychological characteristics of humans. Many of these expectations may not hold true of posthuman persons. When human nature changes, new ways of organizing a society may become feasible. We may hope to form a clearer understanding of what those new possibilities are as we observe the seeds of transhumanity develop.</p>
</div>
</div>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="will-posthumans-or-superintelligent-machines-pose-a-threat-to-humans-who-arent-augmented"><a href="#will-posthumans-or-superintelligent-machines-pose-a-threat-to-humans-who-arent-augmented">Will posthumans or superintelligent machines pose a threat to humans who aren’t augmented?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>Human society is always at risk from some group deciding to view another group of humans as fit for slavery or slaughter. To counteract such tendencies, modern societies have created laws and institutions, and endowed them with powers of enforcement, that act to prevent groups of citizens from assaulting one another. The efficacy of these institutions does not depend on all citizens having equal capacities. Modern, peaceful societies have large numbers of people with diminished physical or mental capacities along with many other people who may be exceptionally physically strong or healthy or intellectually talented in various ways. Adding people with technologically enhanced capacities to this already broad distribution of ability would not necessarily rip society apart or trigger genocide or enslavement.</p>
<p>A common worry is that inheritable genetic modifications or other human enhancement technologies would lead to two distinct and separate species and that hostilities would inevitably develop between them. The assumptions behind this prediction should be questioned. It is a common theme in fiction because of the opportunities for dramatic conflict, but that is not the same as social, political, and economic plausibility in the real world. It seems more likely that there would be a continuum of differently modified or enhanced individuals, which would overlap with the continuum of as-yet unenhanced humans. The scenario in which “the enhanced” form a pact and then attack “the naturals” makes for exciting science fiction but is not necessarily the most plausible outcome. Even today, the segment containing the tallest 90 percent of the population could, in principle, get together and kill or enslave the shorter decile. That this does not happen suggests that a well-organized society can hold together even if it contains many possible coalitions of people sharing some attribute such that, if they unified under one banner, would make them capable of exterminating the rest.</p>
<p>To note that the extreme case of a war between human and posthuman persons is not the most likely scenario is not to say that there are no legitimate social concerns about the steps that may take us closer to posthumanity. Inequity, discrimination, and stigmatization – against or on behalf of modified people – could become serious issues. Transhumanists would argue that these (potential) social problems call for social remedies. (One case study of how contemporary technology can change important aspects of someone’s identify is sex reassignment. The experiences of transsexuals show that some cultures still have work to do in becoming more accepting of diversity.) This is a task that we can begin to tackle now by fostering a climate of tolerance and acceptance towards those who are different from ourselves. We can also act to strengthen those institutions that prevent violence and protect human rights, for instance by building stable democratic traditions and constitutions and by expanding the rule of law to the international plane.</p>
<p>What about the hypothetical case in which someone intends to create, or turn themselves into, a being of so radically enhanced capacities that a single one or a small group of such individuals would be capable of taking over the planet? This is clearly not a situation that is likely to arise in the imminent future, but one can imagine that, perhaps in a few decades, the prospective creation of superintelligent machines could raise this kind of concern. The would-be creator of a new life form with such surpassing capabilities would have an obligation to ensure that the proposed being is free from psychopathic tendencies and, more generally, that it has humane inclinations. For example, a super­intelligence should be built with a clear goal structure that has friendliness to humans as its top goal. Before running such a program, the builders of a super­intelligence should be required to make a strong case that launching it would be safer than alternative courses of action.</p>
</div>
</div>
<h4>References:</h4>
<ul>
<li>Eliezer Yudkowsky, <a href="http://intelligence.org/files/CFAI.pdf">Creating Friendly AI 1.0: The Analysis and Design of Benevolent Goal Architectures</a> (2001)</li>
</ul>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<h2 class="h1" id="technologies-and-projections"><a href="#technologies-and-projections">Technologies and Projections</a></h2>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="biotechnology-genetic-engineering-stem-cells-and-cloning"><a href="#biotechnology-genetic-engineering-stem-cells-and-cloning">Biotechnology, genetic engineering, stem cells, and cloning</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>What are they and what are they good for?</p>
<p>Biotechnology is the application of techniques and methods based on the biological sciences. It encompasses such diverse enterprises as brewing, manufacture of human insulin, interferon, and human growth hormone, medical diagnostics, cell cloning and reproductive cloning, the genetic modification of crops, bioconversion of organic waste and the use of genetically altered bacteria in the cleanup of oil spills, stem cell research and much more. Genetic engineering is the area of biotechnology concerned with the directed alteration of genetic material.</p>
<p>Biotechnology already has countless applications in industry, agriculture, and medicine. It is a hotbed of research. The completion of the human genome project – a “rough draft” of the entire human genome was published in the year 2000 – was a scientific milestone by anyone’s standards. Research is now shifting to decoding the functions and interactions of all these different genes and to developing applications based on this information.</p>
<p>The potential medical benefits are too many to list; researchers are working on every common disease, with varying degrees of success. Progress takes place not only in the development of drugs and diagnostics but also in the creation of better tools and research methodologies, which in turn accelerates progress. When considering what developments are likely over the long term, such improvements in the research process itself must be factored in. The human genome project was completed ahead of schedule, largely because the initial predictions underestimated the degree to which instrumentation technology would improve during the course of the project. At the same time, one needs to guard against the tendency to hype every latest advance. (Remember all those breakthrough cancer cures that we never heard of again?) Moreover, even in cases where the early promise is borne out, it usually takes ten years to get from proof-of-concept to successful commercialization.</p>
<p>Genetic therapies are of two sorts: somatic and germ-line. In somatic gene therapy, a virus is typically used as a vector to insert genetic material into the cells of the recipient’s body. The effects of such interventions do not carry over into the next generation. Germ-line genetic therapy is performed on sperm or egg cells, or on the early zygote, and can be inheritable. (Embryo screening, in which embryos are tested for genetic defects or other traits and then selectively implanted, can also count as a kind of germ-line intervention.) Human gene therapy, except for some forms of embryo screening, is still experimental. Nonetheless, it holds promise for the prevention and treatment of many diseases, as well as for uses in enhancement medicine. The potential scope of genetic medicine is vast: virtually all disease and all human traits – intelligence, extroversion, conscientiousness, physical appearance, etc. – involve genetic predispositions. Single-gene disorders, such as cystic fibrosis, sickle cell anemia, and Huntington’s disease are likely to be among the first targets for genetic intervention. Polygenic traits and disorders, ones in which more than one gene is implicated, may follow later (although even polygenic conditions can sometimes be influenced in a beneficial direction by targeting a single gene).</p>
<p>Stem cell research, another scientific frontier, offers great hopes for regenerative medicine. Stem cells are undifferentiated (unspecialized) cells that can renew themselves and give rise to one or more specialized cell types with specific functions in the body. By growing such cells in culture, or steering their activity in the body, it will be possible to grow replacement tissues for the treatment of degenerative disorders, including heart disease, Parkinson’s, Alzheimer’s, diabetes, and many others. It may also be possible to grow entire organs from stem cells for use in transplantation. Embryonic stem cells seem to be especially versatile and useful, but research is also ongoing into adult stem cells and the “reprogramming” of ordinary cells so that they can be turned back into stem cells with pluripotent capabilities.</p>
<p>The term “human cloning” covers both therapeutic and reproductive uses. In therapeutic cloning, a preimplantation embryo (also known as a “blastocyst” – a hollow ball consisting of 30-150 undifferentiated cells) is created via cloning, from which embryonic stem cells could be extracted and used for therapy. Because these cloned stem cells are genetically identical to the patient, the tissues or organs they would produce could be implanted without eliciting an immune response from the patient’s body, thereby overcoming a major hurdle in transplant medicine. Reproductive cloning, by contrast, would mean the birth of a child who is genetically identical to the cloned parent: in effect, a younger identical twin.</p>
<p>Everybody recognizes the benefit to ailing patients and their families that come from curing specific diseases. Transhumanists emphasize that, in order to seriously prolong the healthy life span, we also need to develop ways to slow aging or to replace senescent cells and tissues. Gene therapy, stem cell research, therapeutic cloning, and other areas of medicine that have the potential to deliver these benefits deserve a high priority in the allocation of research monies.</p>
<p>Biotechnology can be seen as a special case of the more general capabilities that nanotechnology will eventually provide (see <a href="#what-is-molecular-nanotechnology">“What is molecular nanotechnology?”</a>).</p>
</div>
</div>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="what-is-molecular-nanotechnology"><a href="#what-is-molecular-nanotechnology">What is molecular nanotechnology?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>Molecular nanotechnology is an anticipated manufacturing technology that will make it possible to build complex three-dimensional structures to atomic specification using chemical reactions directed by nonbiological machinery. In molecular manufacturing, each atom would go to a selected place, bonding with other atoms in a precisely designated manner. Nanotechnology promises to give us thorough control of the structure of matter.</p>
<p>Since most of the stuff around us and inside us is composed of atoms and gets its characteristic properties from the placement of these atoms, the ability to control the structure of matter on the atomic scale has many applications. As K. Eric Drexler wrote in Engines of Creation, the first book on nanotechnology (published in 1986):</p>
<p>Coal and diamonds, sand and computer chips, cancer and healthy tissue: throughout history, variations in the arrangement of atoms have distinguished the cheap from the cherished, the diseased from the healthy. Arranged one way, atoms make up soil, air, and water arranged another, they make up ripe strawberries. Arranged one way, they make up homes and fresh air; arranged another, they make up ash and smoke.</p>
<p>Nanotechnology, by making it possible to rearrange atoms effectively, will enable us to transform coal into diamonds, sand into supercomputers, and to remove pollution from the air and tumors from healthy tissue.</p>
<p>Central to Drexler’s vision of nanotechnology is the concept of the assembler. An assembler would be a molecular construction device. It would have one or more submicroscopic robotic arms under computer control. The arms would be capable of holding and placing reactive compounds so as to positionally control the precise location at which a chemical reaction takes place. The assembler arms would grab a molecule (but not necessarily individual atoms) and add it to a work-piece, constructing an atomically precise object step by step. An advanced assembler would be able to make almost any chemically stable structure. In particular, it would be able to make a copy of itself. Since assemblers could replicate themselves, they would be easy to produce in large quantities.</p>
<p>There is a biological parallel to the assembler: the ribosome. Ribosomes are the tiny construction machines (a few thousand cubic nanometers big) in our cells that manufacture all the proteins used in all living things on Earth. They do this by assembling amino acids, one by one, into precisely determined sequences. These structures then fold up to form a protein. The blueprint that specifies the order of amino acids, and thus indirectly the final shape of the protein, is called messenger RNA. The messenger RNA is in turned determined by our DNA, which can be viewed (somewhat simplistically) as an instruction tape for protein synthesis. Nanotechnology will generalize the ability of ribosomes so that virtually any chemically stable structure can be built, including devices and materials that resemble nothing in nature.</p>
<p>Mature nanotechnology will transform manufacturing into a software problem. To build something, all you will need is a detailed design of the object you want to make and a sequence of instructions for its construction. Rare or expensive raw materials are generally unnecessary; the atoms required for the construction of most kinds of nanotech devices exist in abundance in nature. Dirt, for example, is full of useful atoms.</p>
<p>By working in large teams, assemblers and more specialized nanomachines will be able to build large objects quickly. Consequently, while nanomachines may have features on the scale of a billionth of a meter – a nanometer – the products could be as big as space vehicles or even, in a more distant future, the size of planets.</p>
<p>Because assemblers will be able to copy themselves, nanotech products will have low marginal production costs – perhaps on the same order as familiar commodities from nature’s own self-reproducing molecular machinery such as firewood, hay, or potatoes. By ensuring that each atom is properly placed, assemblers would manufacture products of high quality and reliability. Leftover molecules would be subject to this strict control, making the manufacturing process extremely clean.</p>
<p>The speed with which designs and instruction lists for making useful objects can be developed will determine the speed of progress after the creation of the first full-blown assembler. Powerful software for molecular modeling and design will accelerate development, possibly assisted by specialized engineering AI. Another accessory that might be especially useful in the early stages after the assembler-breakthrough is the disassembler, a device that can disassemble an object while creating a three-dimensional map of its molecular configuration. Working in concert with an assembler, it could function as a kind of 3D Xerox machine: a device for making atomically exact replicas of almost any existing solid object within reach.</p>
<p>Molecular nanotechnology will ultimately make it possible to construct compact computing systems performing at least 1021 operations per second; machine parts of any size made of nearly flawless diamond; cell-repair machines that can enter cells and repair most kinds of damage, in all likelihood including frostbite (see <a href="#what-is-cryonics-isnt-the-probability-of-success-too-small">“What is cryonics? Isn’t the probability of success too small?”</a>); personal manufacturing and recycling appliances; and automated production systems that can double capital stock in a few hours or less. It is also likely to make uploading possible (see <a href="#what-is-uploading">“What is uploading?”</a>).</p>
<p>A key challenge in realizing these prospects is the bootstrap problem: how to build the first assembler. There are several promising routes. One is to improve current proximal probe technology. An atomic force microscope can drag individual atoms along a surface. Two physicists at IBM Almaden Labs in California illustrated this in 1989 when they used such a microscope to arrange 35 xenon atoms to spell out the trademark “I-B-M”, creating the world’s smallest logo. Future proximal probes might have more degrees of freedom and the ability to pick up and deposit reactive compounds in a controlled fashion.</p>
<p>Another route to the first assembler is synthetic chemistry. Cleverly designed chemical building blocks might be made to self-assemble in solution phase into machine parts. Final assembly of these parts might then be made with a proximal probe.</p>
<p>Yet another route is biochemistry. It might be possible to use ribosomes to make assemblers of more generic capabilities. Many biomolecules have properties that might be explored in the early phases of nanotechnology. For example, interesting structures, such as branches, loops, and cubes, have been made by DNA. DNA could also serve as a “tag” on other molecules, causing them to bind only to designated compounds displaying a complementary tag, thus providing a degree of control over what molecular complexes will form in a solution.</p>
<p>Combinations of these approaches are of course also possible. The fact that there are multiple promising routes adds to the likelihood that success will eventually be attained.</p>
<p>That assemblers of general capabilities are consistent with the laws of chemistry was shown by Drexler in his technical book Nanosystems in 1992. This book also established some lower bounds on the capabilities of mature nanotechnology. Medical applications of nanotechnology were first explored in detail by Robert A. Freitas Jr. in his monumental work <a href="http://www.nanomedicine.com/NMI.htm">Nanomedicine</a>, the first volume of which came out in 1999. Today, nanotech is a hot research field. The U.S. government spent more than 600 million dollars on its National Nanotechnology Initiative in 2002. Other countries have similar programs, and private investment is ample. However, only a small part of the funding goes to projects of direct relevance to the development of assembler-based nanotechnology; most of it is for more humdrum, near-term objectives.</p>
<p>While it seems fairly well established that molecular nanotechnology is in principle possible, it is harder to determine how long it will take to develop. A common guess among the cognoscenti is that the first assembler may be built around the year 2018, give or take a decade, but there is large scope for diverging opinion on the upper side of that estimate.</p>
<p>Because the ramifications of nanotechnology are immense, it is imperative that serious thought be given to this topic now. If nanotechnology were to be abused the consequences could be devastating. Society needs to prepare for the assembler breakthrough and do advance planning to minimize the risks associated with it (see e.g. <a href="#arent-these-future-technologies-very-risky-could-they-even-cause-our-extinction">“Aren’t these future technologies very risky? Could they even cause our extinction?”</a>). Several organizations are working to preparing the world for nanotechnology, the oldest and largest being the Foresight Institute.</p>
</div>
</div>
<h4>References:</h4>
<ul>
<li>K. Eric Drexler, <em><a href="https://web.archive.org/web/20200309082550/http://e-drexler.com/p/06/00/EOC_Cover.html">Engines of Creation: The Coming Era of Nanotechnology</a></em>, (New York: Anchor Books, 1986)</li>
<li>K. Eric Drexler, <em>Nanosystems: Molecular Machinery, Manufacturing, and Computation</em>, (New York: John Wiley & Sons, Inc., 1992)</li>
<li>Robert A. Freitas Jr., <em><a href="http://www.nanomedicine.com/NMI.htm">Nanomedicine, Volume I: Basic Capabilities.</a></em> (Georgetown, Texas: Landes Bioscience, 1999)</li>
<li><a href="https://foresight.org/">Foresight Institute</a></li>
</ul>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="what-is-superintelligence"><a href="#what-is-superintelligence">What is super­intelligence?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>A superintelligent intellect (a super­intelligence, sometimes called “ultraintelligence”) is one that has the capacity to radically outperform the best human brains in practically every field, including scientific creativity, general wisdom, and social skills.</p>
<p>Sometimes a distinction is made between weak and strong super­intelligence. Weak super­intelligence is what you would get if you could run a human intellect at an accelerated clock speed, such as by uploading it to a fast computer (see <a href="#what-is-uploading">“What is uploading?”</a>). If the upload’s clock-rate were a thousand times that of a biological brain, it would perceive reality as being slowed down by a factor of a thousand. It would think a thousand times more thoughts in a given time interval than its biological counterpart.</p>
<p>Strong super­intelligence refers to an intellect that is not only faster than a human brain but also smarter in a qualitative sense. No matter how much you speed up your dog’s brain, you’re not going to get the equivalent of a human intellect. Analogously, there might be kinds of smartness that wouldn’t be accessible to even very fast human brains given their current capacities. Something as simple as increasing the size or connectivity of our neuronal networks might give us some of these capacities. Other improvements may require wholesale reorganization of our cognitive architecture or the addition of new layers of cognition on top of the old ones.</p>
<p>However, the distinction between weak and strong super­intelligence may not be clear-cut. A sufficiently long-lived human who didn’t make any errors and had a sufficient stack of scrap paper at hand could in principle compute any Turing computable function. (According to Church’s thesis, the class of Turing computable functions is identical to the class of physically computable functions.)</p>
<p>Many but not all transhumanists expect that super­intelligence will be created within the first half of this century. Super­intelligence requires two things: hardware and software.</p>
<p>Chip-manufacturers planning the next generation of microprocessors commonly rely on a well-known empirical regularity known as Moore’s Law. In its original 1965-formulation by Intel co-founder Gordon Moore, it stated that the number of components on a chip doubled every year. In contemporary use, the “law” is commonly understood as referring more generally to a doubling of computing power, or of computing power per dollar. For the past couple of years, the doubling time has hovered between 18 months and two years.</p>
<p>The human brain’s processing power is difficult to determine precisely, but common estimates range from 1014 instructions per second (IPS) up to 1017 IPS or more. The lower estimate, derived by Carnegie Mellon robotics professor Hans Moravec, is based on the computing power needed to replicate the signal processing performed by the human retina and assumes a significant degree of software optimization. The 1017 IPS estimate is obtained by multiplying the number of neurons in a human brain (~100 billion) with the average number of synapses per neuron (~1,000) and with the average spike rate (~100 Hz), and assuming ~10 instructions to represent the effect on one action potential traversing one synapse. An even higher estimate would be obtained e.g. if one were to suppose that functionally relevant and computationally intensive processing occurs within compartments of a dendrite tree.</p>
<p>Most experts, Moore included, think that computing power will continue to double about every 18 months for at least another two decades. This expectation is based in part on extrapolation from the past and in part on consideration of developments currently underway in laboratories. The fastest computer under construction is IBM’s Blue Gene/L, which when it is ready in 2005 is expected to perform ~2*1014 IPS. Thus it appears quite likely that human-equivalent hardware will have been achieved within not much more than a couple of decades.</p>
<p>How long it will take to solve the software problem is harder to estimate. One possibility is that progress in computational neuroscience will teach us about the computational architecture of the human brain and what learning rules it employs. We can then implement the same algorithms on a computer. In this approach, the super­intelligence would not be completely specified by the programmers but would instead have to grow by learning from experience the same way a human infant does. An alternative approach would be to use genetic algorithms and methods from classical AI. This might result in a super­intelligence that bears no close resemblance to a human brain. At the opposite extreme, we could seek to create a super­intelligence by uploading a human intellect and then accelerating and enhancing it (see <a href="#what-is-uploading">“What is uploading?”</a>). The outcome of this might be a super­intelligence that is a radically upgraded version of one particular human mind.</p>
<p>The arrival of super­intelligence will clearly deal a heavy blow to anthropocentric worldviews. Much more important than its philosophical implications, however, would be its practical effects. Creating super­intelligence may be the last invention that humans will ever need to make, since super­intelligences could themselves take care of further scientific and technological development. They would do so more effectively than humans. Biological humanity would no longer be the smartest life form on the block.</p>
<p>The prospect of super­intelligence raises many big issues and concerns that we should think deeply about in advance of its actual development. The paramount question is: What can be done to maximize the chances that the arrival of super­intelligence will benefit rather than harm us? The range of expertise needed to address this question extends far beyond the community of AI researchers. Neuroscientists, economists, cognitive scientists, computer scientists, philosophers, ethicists, sociologists, science-fiction writers, military strategists, politicians, legislators, and many others will have to pool their insights if we are to deal wisely with what may be the most important task our species will ever have to tackle.</p>
<p>Many transhumanists would like to become superintelligent themselves. This is obviously a long-term and uncertain goal, but it might be achievable either through uploading and subsequent enhancement or through the gradual augmentation of our biological brains, by means of future nootropics (cognitive enhancement drugs), cognitive techniques, IT tools (e.g. wearable computers, smart agents, information filtering systems, visualization software, etc.), neural-computer interfaces, or brain implants.</p>
</div>
</div>
<h4>References:</h4>
<ul>
<li>Hans Moravec, <em>Mind Children</em> (Harvard: Harvard University Press, 1989)</li>
<li>Nick Bostrom, <a href="https://www.nickbostrom.com/superintelligence.html">“How Long Before Super­intelligence?”</a>, <em>International Journal of Futures Studies</em> Vol. 2. (1998)</li>
</ul>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="what-is-virtual-reality"><a href="#what-is-virtual-reality">What is virtual reality?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>A virtual reality is a simulated environment that your senses perceive as real.</p>
<p>Theatre, opera, cinema, television can be regarded as precursors to virtual reality. The degree of immersion (the feeling of “being there”) that you experience when watching television is quite limited. Watching football on TV doesn’t really compare to being in the stadium. There are several reasons for this. For starters, even a big screen doesn’t fill up your entire visual field. The number of pixels even on high-resolution screens is also too small (typically 1280*1224 rather than about 5000*5000 as would be needed in a flawless wide-angle display). Further, 3D vision is lacking, as is position tracking and focus effects (in reality, the picture on your retina changes continually as your head and eyeballs are moving). To achieve greater realism, a system should ideally include more sensory modalities, such as 3D sound (through headphones) to hear the crowd roaring, and tactile stimulation through a whole-body haptic interface so that you don’t have to miss out on the sensation of sitting on a cold, hard bench for hours.</p>
<p>An essential element of immersion is interactivity. Watching TV is typically a passive experience. Full-blown virtual reality, by contrast, will be interactive. You will be able to move about in a virtual world, pick up objects you see, and communicate with people you meet. (A real football experience crucially includes the possibility of shouting abuse at the referee.) To enable interactivity, the system must have sensors that pick up on your movements and utterances and adjust the presentation to incorporate the consequences of your actions.</p>
<p>Virtual worlds can be modeled on physical realities. If you are participating in a remote event through VR, as in the example of the imagined football spectator, you are said to be telepresent at that event. Virtual environments can also be wholly artificial, like cartoons, and have no particular counterpart in physical reality. Another possibility, known as augmented reality, is to have your perception of your immediate surroundings partially overlaid with simulated elements. For example, by wearing special glasses, nametags could be made to appear over the heads of guests at a dinner party, or you could opt to have annoying billboard advertisements blotted out from your view.</p>
<p>Many users of today’s VR systems experience “simulator sickness,” with symptoms ranging from unpleasantness and disorientation to headaches, nausea, and vomiting. Simulator sickness arises because different sensory systems provide conflicting cues. For example, the visual system may provide strong cues of self-motion while the vestibular system in your inner ear tells your brain that your head is stationary. Heavy head-mounted display helmets and lag times between tracking device and graphics update can also cause discomfort. Creating good VR that overcomes these problems is technically challenging.</p>
<p>Primitive virtual realities have been around for some time. Early applications included training modules for pilots and military personnel. Increasingly, VR is used in computer gaming. Partly because VR is computationally very intensive, simulations are still quite crude. As computational power increases, and as sensors, effectors and displays improve, VR could begin to approximate physical reality in terms of fidelity and interactivity.</p>
<p>In the long run, VR could unlock limitless possibilities for human creativity. We could construct artificial experiential worlds, in which the laws of physics can be suspended, that would appear as real as physical reality to participants. People could visit these worlds for work, entertainment, or to socialize with friends who may be living on the opposite site of the globe. Uploads (see <a href="#what-is-uploading">“What is uploading?”</a>), who could interact with simulated environments directly without the need of a mechanical interface, might spend most of their time in virtual realities.</p>
</div>
</div>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="what-is-cryonics-isnt-the-probability-of-success-too-small"><a href="#what-is-cryonics-isnt-the-probability-of-success-too-small">What is cryonics? Isn’t the probability of success too small?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>Cryonics is an experimental medical procedure that seeks to save lives by placing in low-temperature storage persons who cannot be treated with current medical procedures and who have been declared legally dead, in the hope that technological progress will eventually make it possible to revive them.</p>
<p>For cryonics to work today, it is not necessary that we can currently reanimate cryo-preserved patients (which we cannot). All that is needed is that we can preserve patients in a state sufficiently intact that some possible technology, developed in the future, will one day be able to repair the freezing damage and reverse the original cause of deanimation. Only half of the complete cryonics procedure can be scrutinized today; the other half cannot be performed until the (perhaps distant) future.</p>
<p>What we know now is that it is possible to stabilize a patient’s condition by cooling him or her in liquid nitrogen (- 196 C°). A considerable amount of cell damage is caused by the freezing process. This injury can be minimized by following suspension protocols that involve suffusing the deanimated body with cryoprotectants. The formation of damaging ice crystals can even be suppressed altogether in a process known as vitrification, in which the patient’s body is turned into a kind of glass. This might sound like an improbable treatment, but the purpose of cryonics is to preserve the structure of life rather than the processes of life, because the life processes can in principle be re-started as long as the information encoded in the structural properties of the body, in particular the brain, are sufficiently preserved. Once frozen, the patient can be stored for millennia with virtually no further tissue degradation.</p>
<p>Many experts in molecular nanotechnology believe that in its mature stage nanotechnology will enable the revival of cryonics patients. Hence, it is possible that the suspended patients could be revived in as little as a few decades from now. The uncertainty about the ultimate technical feasibility of reanimation may very well be dwarfed by the uncertainty in other factors, such as the possibility that you deanimate in the wrong kind of way (by being lost at sea, for example, or by having the brain’s information content erased by Alzheimer’s disease), that your cryonics company goes bust, that civilization collapses, or that people in the future won’t be interested in reviving you. So, a cryonics contract is far short of a survival guarantee. As a cryonicist saying goes, being cryonically suspended is the second worst thing that can happen to you.</p>
<p>When we consider the procedures that are routine today and how they might have been viewed in (say) the 1700s, we can begin to see how difficult it is to make a well-founded argument that future medical technology will never be able to reverse the injuries that occur during cryonic suspension. By contrast, your chances of a this-worldly comeback if you opt for one of the popular alternative treatments – such as cremation or burial – are zero. Seen in this light, signing up for cryonics, which is usually done by making a cryonics firm one of the beneficiaries of your life insurance, can look like a reasonable insurance policy. If it doesn’t work, you would be dead anyway. If it works, it may save your life. Your saved life would then likely be extremely long and healthy, given how advanced the state of medicine must be to revive you.</p>
<p>By no means are all transhumanists signed up for cryonics, but a significant fraction finds that, for them, a cost-benefit analysis justifies the expense. Becoming a cryonicist, however, requires courage: the courage to confront the possibility of your own death, and the courage to resist the peer-pressure from the large portion of the population which currently espouses deathist values and advocates complacency in the face of a continual, massive loss of human life.</p>
</div>
</div>
<h4>References:</h4>
<ul>
<li>Ralph C. Merkle, <a href="http://www.merkle.com/cryo/techFeas.html">“The Molecular Repair of the Brain”</a>, <em>Cryonics Magazine</em> Vol. 15, No’s 1 & 2. (1994)</li>
</ul>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="what-is-uploading"><a href="#what-is-uploading">What is uploading?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">
<p>Uploading (sometimes called “downloading”, “mind uploading” or “brain reconstruction”) is the process of transferring an intellect from a biological brain to a computer.</p>
<p>One way of doing this might be by first scanning the synaptic structure of a particular brain and then implementing the same computations in an electronic medium. A brain scan of sufficient resolution could be produced by disassembling the brain atom for atom by means of nanotechnology. Other approaches, such as analyzing pieces of the brain slice by slice in an electron microscope with automatic image processing have also been proposed. In addition to mapping the connection pattern among the 100 billion-or-so neurons, the scan would probably also have to register some of the functional properties of each of the synaptic interconnections, such as the efficacy of the connection and how stable it is over time (e.g. whether it is short-term or long-term potentiated). Non-local modulators such as neurotransmitter concentrations and hormone balances may also need to be represented, although such parameters likely contain much less data than the neuronal network itself.</p>
<p>In addition to a good three-dimensional map of a brain, uploading will require progress in neuroscience to develop functional models of each species of neuron (how they map input stimuli to outgoing action potentials, and how their properties change in response to activity in learning). It will also require a powerful computer to run the upload, and some way for the upload to interact with the external world or with a virtual reality. (Providing input/output or a virtual reality for the upload appears easy in comparison to the other challenges.)</p>
<p>An alternative hypothetical uploading method would proceed more gradually: one neuron could be replaced by an implant or by a simulation in a computer outside of the body. Then another neuron, and so on, until eventually the whole cortex has been replaced and the person’s thinking is implemented on entirely artificial hardware. (To do this for the whole brain would almost certainly require nanotechnology.)</p>
<p>A distinction is sometimes made between destructive uploading, in which the original brain is destroyed in the process, and non-destructive uploading, in which the original brain is preserved intact alongside the uploaded copy. It is a matter of debate under what conditions personal identity would be preserved in destructive uploading. Many philosophers who have studied the problem think that at least under some conditions, an upload of your brain would be you. A widely accepted position is that you survive so long as certain information patterns are conserved, such as your memories, values, attitudes, and emotional dispositions, and so long as there is causal continuity so that earlier stages of yourself help determine later stages of yourself. Views differ on the relative importance of these two criteria, but they can both be satisfied in the case of uploading. For the continuation of personhood, on this view, it matters little whether you are implemented on a silicon chip inside a computer or in that gray, cheesy lump inside your skull, assuming both implementations are conscious.</p>
<p>Tricky cases arise, however, if we imagine that several similar copies are made of your uploaded mind. Which one of them is you? Are they all you, or are none of them you? Who owns your property? Who is married to your spouse? Philosophical, legal, and ethical challenges abound. Maybe these will become hotly debated political issues later in this century.</p>
<p>A common misunderstanding about uploads is that they would necessarily be “disembodied” and that this would mean that their experiences would be impoverished. Uploading according to this view would be the ultimate escapism, one that only neurotic body-loathers could possibly feel tempted by. But an upload’s experience could in principle be identical to that of a biological human. An upload could have a virtual (simulated) body giving the same sensations and the same possibilities for interaction as a non-simulated body. With advanced virtual reality, uploads could enjoy food and drink, and upload sex could be as gloriously messy as one could wish. And uploads wouldn’t have to be confined to virtual reality: they could interact with people on the outside and even rent robot bodies in order to work in or explore physical reality.</p>
<p>Personal inclinations regarding uploading differ. Many transhumanists have a pragmatic attitude: whether they would like to upload or not depends on the precise conditions in which they would live as uploads and what the alternatives are. (Some transhumanists may also doubt whether uploading will be possible.) Advantages of being an upload would include:</p>
<p>Uploads would not be subject to biological senescence.</p>
<p>Back-up copies of uploads could be created regularly so that you could be re-booted if something bad happened. (Thus your lifespan would potentially be as long as the universe’s.)</p>
<p>You could potentially live much more economically as an upload since you wouldn’t need physical food, housing, transportation, etc.</p>
<p>If you were running on a fast computer, you would think faster than in a biological implementation. For instance, if you were running on a computer a thousand times more powerful than a human brain, then you would think a thousand times faster (and the external world would appear to you as if it were slowed down by a factor of a thousand). You would thus get to experience more subjective time, and live more, during any given day.</p>
<p>You could travel at the speed of light as an information pattern, which could be convenient in a future age of large-scale space settlements.</p>
<p>Radical cognitive enhancements would likely be easier to implement in an upload than in an organic brain.</p>
<p>A couple of other points about uploading:</p>
<p>Uploading should work for cryonics patients provided their brains are preserved in a sufficiently intact state.</p>
<p>Uploads could reproduce extremely quickly (simply by making copies of themselves). This implies that resources could very quickly become scarce unless reproduction is regulated.</p>
</div>
</div>
<a class="back-to-top" href="#table-of-contents">Back ↑</a>
</div>
<div itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Question">
<h3 class="h2" itemprop="name" id="what-is-the-singularity"><a href="#what-is-the-singularity">What is the singularity?</a></h3>
<div itemprop="suggestedAnswer acceptedAnswer" itemscope itemtype="http://schema.org/Answer">
<div itemprop="text">